Dual Process Theory and Auxiliary Hypotheses
The stripped-down dual process theory (see A Dual Process Theory of Ethical Judgement) requires at least one auxiliary hypothesis in order to relate it to available evidence. At least six auxiliary hypotheses have been proposed. Which should we accept?
If the video isn’t working you could also watch it on youtube. Or you can view just the slides (no audio or video).
This recording is also available on stream (no ads; search enabled).
If the slides are not working, or you prefer them full screen, please try this link. The recording is available on stream and youtube.
Notes
Proponents of dual process theories of ethical judgments tend to offer complex sets of hypotheses which go far beyond the core idea of a dual process theory and are not all equally well supported by evidence (for two examples, see Green and Kumar in A Dual Process Theory of Ethical Judgement).
Since the hypotheses that are associated with different proposals can be isolated and tested separately, combining them yields something more like a parlay bet than a theory. Better to keep them separate.
What Is the Core Idea
Just this and nothing more.
Two (or more) ethical processes are distinct in this sense: the conditions which influence whether they occur, and which outputs they generate, do not completely overlap.
One process is faster than another: it makes fewer demands on scarce cognitive resources such as attention, inhibitory control and working memory.
Because much of the available evidence involves observations of just one response to a moral scenario (typically a verbal judgement1), additional, auxiliary hypotheses are needed to generate predictions linked to the currently available evidence. But which auxiliary hypothesis should we adopt?
What Are the Candidate Auxiliary Hypotheses?
At least six candidates for auxiliary hypotheses can be found in the existing literature (and there are probably many more):
id | fast | slow | source |
---|---|---|---|
1. | never consequentialist2 | sometimes consequentialist | Greene (2014) |
2. | always deontological3 | sometimes not deontological | Greene (2014)4 |
3. | always only act-types | sometimes not only act-types | Cushman (2013) |
4. | never distal outcomes | sometimes distal outcomes | Cushman (2013)5 |
5. | model-free | model-based | Cushman (2013) |
6. | affective | cognitive | Greene (2014) |
UPDATE A further candidate auxiliary hypothesis might concern the distinction between personal and impersonal. Since this introduces even more problems than we will eventually have to face (McGuire, Langdon, Coltheart, & Mackenzie, 2009), it does not appear to be a good bet as things stand.
Which Auxiliary Hypothesis to Choose?
I propose that we use just one auxiliary hypothesis, which is a version of (4) above:
Only the slow process ever flexibly and rapidly takes into account differences in the more distal outcomes of an action.
This auxiliary hypothesis has two virtues. Together with the stripped-down dual process theory, it generates nearly all the predictions for which we currently have good evidence. And it cannot be significantly weakened while still doing this.
Glossary
Since automaticity and cognitive efficiency are matters of degree, it is only strictly correct to identify some processes as faster than others.
The fast-slow distinction has been variously characterised in ways that do not entirely overlap (even individual author have offered differing characterisations at different times; e.g. Kahneman, 2013; Morewedge & Kahneman, 2010; Kahneman & Klein, 2009; Kahneman, 2002): as its advocates stress, it is a rough-and-ready tool, not the basis for a rigorous theory.
References
-
Measures like response time, movement trajectory, proactive eye gaze or pupil dilation do not seem to have caught on in moral psychology despite being used to good effect in supporting dual process theories in other domains including social cognition (see Wel, Sebanz, & Knoblich, 2014 or Edwards & Low, 2017 for some examples). ↩
-
In this context, the term ‘consequentialist’ is short for characteristically consequentialist. ↩
-
In this context, the term ‘consequentialist’ is short for characteristically deontological. ↩
-
Greene (2014) does not explicitly separate this and the first candidate, (1). But they are clearly distinct. ↩
-
Cushman (2013) phrases the distinction in terms of actions and outcomes. This is potentially confusing if, like Davidson (1971), you think that actions are individuated by their outcomes. But it is clear from the discussion that Cushman’s distinction concerns a contrast between more proximal outcomes and more distal outcomes. Note also that Cushman does not explicitly distinguish this and the third candidate, (3); perhaps the distinction is too minor to consider. ↩